cantors-attic

Climb into Cantor’s Attic, where you will find infinities large and small. We aim to provide a comprehensive resource of information about all notions of mathematical infinity.

View the Project on GitHub neugierde/cantors-attic

Quick navigation
The upper attic
The middle attic
The lower attic
The parlour
The playroom
The library
The cellar

Sources
Cantor's Attic (original site)
Joel David Hamkins blog post about the Attic
Latest working snapshot at the wayback machine

Club sets and stationary sets

Closed and unbounded subsets of ordinals, more commonly referred to as club sets, play a prominent role in modern set theory. We intuitively think of clubs as the “large” subsets of $\kappa$ and the stationary subsets as the “not small” subsets of $\kappa$, though this is sort of a boring way to look at them. They arise from considering the natural topology on the class of ordinals and often exhibit substantial reflection properties.

Given an ordinal $\kappa$, the basic open intervals are pairs of ordinals $(\alpha, \beta)=\{\gamma : \alpha <\gamma < \beta\}$ where $\beta <\kappa$. Closed intervals are defined similarly, so closed intervals are topologically closed. Considering a typical example of an interval of ordinals $[\lambda, \lambda+1, \lambda+2, \dots)$ it appears there are more successor ordinals than limits, but club (and also stationary) sets favor limit ordinals in the sense that they concentrate on them. Hence the opposite view-point is more useful when considering club sets, i.e., there are “more” limit ordinals.

Club sets

Although the definition can be applied to all infinite ordinals, we assume $\kappa >\omega$ is a regular cardinal for this and subsequent sections.

A set $C\subseteq \kappa$ is closed unbounded or club in $\kappa$ if and only if $C$ is unbounded in $\kappa$: for every $\alpha <\kappa$ there is some $\beta \in C$ with occurring above $\alpha$ in the natural ordering; and $C$ is also closed: if $B\subseteq C$ is bounded in $\kappa$ (i.e., there is some $\gamma\in \kappa$ with $\beta\leq \gamma$ for each $\beta\in B$), then $sup(B)\in C$. If $\lambda < \kappa$ and $ \lambda$ a limit with $C\cap\lambda$ unbounded in $\lambda$, then $\lambda\in C$.

Typical examples club sets include the collection of limit ordinals below $\kappa$, the collection of limits of limit ordinals below $\kappa$, and also all “tails” in $\kappa$: $\{\lambda : \alpha\leq \lambda <\kappa\}$ for each $\alpha <\kappa$. It is fairly straightforward to construct a club subset of $\kappa$. Given a sequence $\langle\gamma_\alpha\rangle_{\alpha < \kappa}$ of ordinals smaller than $\kappa$ arbitrarily pick $\gamma_{\alpha +1}$ also smaller than $\kappa$. At limit stages, take the supremum of the sequence already constructed. It is clear that club subsets of $\kappa$ all have size $\kappa$ and their enumeration functions $f:\kappa\rightarrow\kappa$ are all continuous and increasing.

The intersection of two club subsets of $\kappa$ is also club in $\kappa$. In fact, given any sequence of fewer than $\kappa$-many club subsets of $\kappa$, their intersection is also club in $\kappa$. Further, any collection of fewer than $\kappa$-many club subsets is also closed under diagonal intersections, a fact used in characterizing the stationary subsets of $\kappa$. In particular, the club subsets of $\kappa$ form a filter over $\kappa$. Note that the intersection of $\kappa$-many clubs might be empty, so this filter is not an ultrafilter in general.

Stationary sets

A set $S\subseteq \kappa$ is stationary in $\kappa$ if $S$ intersects all club subsets of $\kappa$. As mentioned above, one intuitively thinks of the collection of stationary subsets of $\kappa$ as the ``not small” subsets of $\kappa$.

Several facts about stationary sets are immediate: all club subsets of $\kappa$ are also stationary in $\kappa$; the supremum of a stationary subset of $\kappa$, is $\kappa$; the intersection of a club set with a stationary set is stationary; if $S$ is a stationary set and also the union of less than $\kappa$-many sets $S_\alpha$, then at least one such set is also stationary, in other words, stationary subsets of $\kappa$ cannot be partitioned into a small number of small sets.

For a given regular cardinal $\kappa$, particular stationary sets

Fodor’s Lemma (improving upon Alexandrov-Urysohn, 1929) is the basic, fundamental result concerning the concept of stationarity. Call a function $f:\kappa\to\kappa$ regressive if $f(\alpha) < \alpha$ for all non-zero ordinals smaller than $\kappa$. Fodor’s lemma reads: If $f$ is a regressive function with domain a stationary subset $S$ of $\kappa$, then there is some subset $S’$ of $S$ on which $f$ is constant.

Using Fodor’s lemma, Solovay proved that each stationary subset of $\kappa$ can be split into two, in fact $\kappa$-many disjoint stationary sets. Another application of Fodor’s lemma is used to prove a result concerning families of sets that are as different as possible, i.e., any two distinct sets in the family have the same intersection. The result is more popularly known as the $\Delta$-system Lemma (originally established by Marczewski): Given a family of finite sets (infinite sets usually require CH), of size $\kappa$ there is a subfamily of size $\kappa$ which forms a $\Delta$-system.

Generalized notions

References

Main library

    This article is a stub. Please help us to improve Cantor's Attic by adding information.